Menu Close
the-natural-process-image

Meeting of minds

Converging on a target of commonly shared competence

No two children, even those learning what is regarded as the same language, have exactly the same experiences of language. Most children have entirely different experiences. And yet they all converge on the same grammar. The same competence is shared. This is known as ‘the logical problem of language acquisition’. Competent speakers can agree or disagree about plays on words and other sorts of jokes and the exact meaning of business contracts and political resolutions and agreements. And if they don’t agree, they can, and often do, argue about the meanings.

People brought up in an English-speaking environment mostly end up agreeing that:

  • There is no difference in meaning between “You believe that it’s true?” and “You believe it’s true?”
  • “The rabbit is ready to eat” means two things, one good for the rabbit, one not.
  • “Mightn’t the ball that won the match that the bookie keeps talking about have been being examined by the umpire?” is meaningful (even if it clunks more than somewhat).

For any language, agreement on such points is possible in principle. This is shown most dramatically in the language development of two normally-developing brothers, Joe and Arthur, two and half years apart in age, analysed more fully and in more detail in the proposal here,. At around two years and ten months,  Joe said “I want to stand on the chair to see what’s happening”. At the same age,  Frank said “I want to sit where Joe’s been sitting.” In both children, these were thes first sentences with multiple embeddings, in both cases with the most deeply embedded clause introduced by an Wh word, what in Joe’s case, and where in Frank’s. In both cases, the structure is completely grammatical with a contracted auxiliary ‘s forming a tensed structure.

Obviously, what Joe was saying was an important part of Frank’s language experience. But while Frank may have taken on board many of Joe’s interests, it does not seem plausible that this extended to such trivial curiosities as the formal structures of their grammar at the same chronological age.

The exactness of the similarity between these structures (only noticed forty years later when the data came to be ansalysed), and their complete grammaticality at a point when the first embeddings were just first appearing, does strongly suggest that there is some significance in them. By the proposal here, these structures signal a critical point in the mastery of ‘Universal Grammar’.

By the same token, this is only possible if the essential structures, are well defined, and not some random chunks of language experience, as proposed by Mike Tomasello (2003), Ben Ambridge (2004), and others.

The end-state

By the proposal here, in a biologically unusual way, the modern human’s acquisition of language necessarily recapitulates evolution. The progress towards agreement on optional variation, ambiguity, and deeply recursieve complexity, can only be based on a particular sequence in the evolution of speech and language. The core of the essential apparatus for speech and language. known as Universal Grammar, UG, is known by most children by the age of three. But as Carol Chomsky (1969) showed, there are subtle aspects of the grammar which are still normally in process at eight, not finally mastered until ten, and sometimes not mastered at all. Nunes (2002) shows that for most children, the final stages of speech acquisition are still in process at eight. And Nunes (2022) confirms Carol Chomsky’s result with observational diary data, construed in a current theoretical framework.

In all cultures, this seemingly extraordinary feat of acquisition is accomplished effortlessly and reliably over this approximate time scale of around ten years. By the mental structure which makes this possible, human beings are different from any other animal.

Do you have an enquiry?